La percepción de daño intencional y su papel en los juicios morales condenatorios
dc.contributor.advisor | Rosas López, Alejandro | spa |
dc.contributor.author | Silva Carrero, Gustavo Adolfo | spa |
dc.contributor.researchgroup | Ética, Comportamiento y Evolución | spa |
dc.date.accessioned | 2020-12-07T17:25:08Z | spa |
dc.date.available | 2020-12-07T17:25:08Z | spa |
dc.date.issued | 2020-12-01 | spa |
dc.description.abstract | En la actualidad existe una controversia generada en el campo de la psicología en torno al contenido básico de los juicios morales. Dicha controversia, por un lado, presenta a los defensores de un único contenido básico, representado en la percepción de daño, sobre el que las distintas culturas moldean sus propias reglas y códigos éticos (Cf. Turiel, 1998) y, por el otro, aparecen los defensores de una concepción culturalista que postula contenidos básicos diversos de la moralidad y que no se limitan al daño (Cf. Shweder, 1990). Ambas propuestas se apoyan en una gran cantidad de estudios empíricos que a lo largo de tres décadas han mantenido el debate vivo y dinámico. Esta investigación presenta un nuevo modelo del dominio moral centrado en las entidades morales que, conciliadoramente, explica la diversidad cultural de la moral y, a la vez, asume el daño intencional como elemento unificador de la moralidad. Así, propongo una concepción amplia de daño moral que tiene en cuenta el perjuicio intencional dirigido a las entidades que habitan cada uno de los ámbitos morales propuestos por Shweder en su clásico modelo Community, Autonomy, Divinity. Mi intención es mostrar que, al resaltar el papel de las entidades morales en el dominio moral y su exposición natural al daño, podemos sostener que el contenido nuclear de los juicios morales se relaciona efectivamente con el daño. | spa |
dc.description.abstract | There is a controversy in the field of psychology about The basic content of moral judgments. On the one hand, this controversy presents the defenders of a single content, manifested in the perception of harm, on which different cultures elaborate their rules and ethical codes (Cf. Turiel 1998). On the other hand, are the defenders of a culturalist conception that postulates manifold contents of morality and that is not limited to harm (Cf. Shweder 1990). Both proposals are supported by a large number of empirical studies that over three decades have kept the debate alive and dynamic. This research presents a new model of the moral domain centered on moral entities, that explains the cultural diversity of morality and assumes intentional harm as a unifying element of morality. Thus, I propose a broad conception of moral harm that considers the intentional harm directed at the entities that inhabit each of the moral codes proposed by Shweder in his model: Community, Autonomy, Divinity. I want to show that, by highlighting the role of moral entities in the moral domain and their natural exposure to harm, we can argue that the core content of moral judgments is related to harm. | spa |
dc.description.additional | Línea de Investigación: Filosofía de las ciencias cognitivas, filosofía experimental, metaética | spa |
dc.description.degreelevel | Doctorado | spa |
dc.format.extent | 164 | spa |
dc.format.mimetype | application/pdf | spa |
dc.identifier.citation | Silva, G. A. (2020). La percepción de daño y su papel en los juicios morales condenatorios. (Tesis de doctorado en Filosofía, Universidad Nacional de Colombia, Bogotá) | spa |
dc.identifier.uri | https://repositorio.unal.edu.co/handle/unal/78682 | |
dc.language.iso | spa | spa |
dc.publisher.branch | Universidad Nacional de Colombia - Sede Bogotá | spa |
dc.publisher.department | Departamento de Filosofía | spa |
dc.publisher.program | Bogotá - Ciencias Humanas - Doctorado en Filosofía | spa |
dc.relation.references | Appiah, K. A. (2005). The ethics of identity. Princeton: Princeton University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Appiah, K. A. (2010). Experimentos de ética. Buenos Aires: Katz Editores. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Aristóteles. (1985). Ética nicomáquea. Madrid: Gredos. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Atran, S. y Norenzayan, A. (2004). Religion’s evolutionary landscape: Counterintuition, commitment, compassion, communion. Behavioral and Brain Cciences, 27(06), 713-730. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Ayer, A. J. (1984). Lenguaje, verdad y lógica. Barcelona: Planeta-Agostini. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Barrett, J. L. (2000). Exploring the natural foundations of religion. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(1), 29-34. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Beck, L. W. (1960). A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Bentham, J. (1988[1781]). The Principles of Moral and Legislation. Amherst, Nueva York: Prometheus Books. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Bentham, J. (2012[1780]). Introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Nabu Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Blair, R. J. R. (1995). A cognitive developmental approach to morality: investigating the psychopath. Cognition, 57(1), 1-29. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Bloom, P. (2007). Religion is natural. Developmental Science, 10(1), 147-151. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Bloom, P. (2009). Descartes’ baby: How the science of child development explains what makes us human. New York: Basic Books. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Boyer, P. (1992). Explaining Religious Ideas: Elements of a Cognitive Approach. Numen, 39(1), 27-57. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Boyer, P. (2000). Evolution of the modern mind and the origins of culture: Religious concepts as a limiting-case. En P. Carruthers y A. Chamberlain (Eds.), Evolution and the Human Mind: Modularity, Language and Meta-Cognition (pp. 93-112). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Brink, D. O. (1997). Moral motivation. Ethics, 108, 4-32. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Bryant, A. (1977). The Anita Bryant story: The survival of our nation’s families and the threat of militant homosexuality. Grand Rapids, MI: Revell. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Callicott, J. B. (1980). Animal liberation. Environmental Ethics, 2, 311-338. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Camps, V. (2017). Breve historia de la ética. Barcelona: RBA Libros. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Caponi, G. (2014). Leyes sin causa y causas sin ley en la explicación biológica. Bogotá: Universidad Nacional de Colombia. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Castano, E. y Giner-Sorolla, R. (2006). Not quite human: Infrahumanization in response to collective responsability for intergroup killing. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90, 804-818. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Caswell, M. (2006). Kant’s Conception of the Highest Good, the Gesinnung, and the Theory of Radical Evil. Kant-Studien, 97(2), 184-209. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Cavalieri, P. (2001). The animal question: Why nonhuman animals deserve human rights. New York: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Chakroff, A., Dungan, J. y Young, L. (2013). Harming ourselves and defiling others: What determines a moral domain? PLoS ONE, 8(9), e74434. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Cohen, J. A. (1992). Power Primer. Psychological Bulletin, 112(1), 155-159. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Cooley, E., Payne, B. K., Cipolli, W., Cameron, C. D., Berger, A. y Gray, K. (2017). The paradox of group mind: “People in a group” have more mind than “a group of people.” Journal of Experimental Psychology, General, 146(5), 691-699. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Copp, D. (1997). Belief, Reason and Motivation: Michael Smith’s The moral problem. Ethics, 106, 33-54. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Curry, O. S. (2016). Morality as Cooperation: A Problem-Centred Approach. En T.K. Shackelford, R.D. Hansen (Eds.), The Evolution of Morality, Evolutionary Psychology. Springer International Publishing Switzerland. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Dennett, D. C. (1996). Kinds of minds: Toward an understanding of consciousness. New York, NY: Basic Books. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Dennett, D. C. (2004). La evolución de la libertad. Barcelona: Paidós. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Dennett, D. C. (2007). Breaking the spell: Religion as a natural phenomenon. New York, NY: Penguin Books. | spa |
dc.relation.references | DeScioli, P. (2008). Investigations into the problems of moral cognition. (Doctoral dissertation, University of Pennsylvania). Recuperado de http://repository.upenn.edu/dissertations/AAI3309424/ | spa |
dc.relation.references | DeScioli, P., Gilbert, S. y Kurzban, R. (2012). Indelible victims and persistent punishers in moral cognition. Psychological Inquiry, 23, 143-149. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Dewey, J. (1939). Theory of valuation. Chicago: University of Chicago. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Dwyer, S. (1999). Moral competence. En K. Murasugi y R. Stainton (Eds.), Philosophy and Linguistics. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Boulder, CO: Westview Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Bueno, G. (2003). El mito de la Izquierda: Las izquierdas y la derecha. Barcelona: Ediciones B. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Burgess, J. A. (2008). Could a Zygote be a Human Being?, Bioethics, vol. Online, 1-10. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Butler, J. (1856). Fifteen sermons preached at the Rolls Chapel. London: Longman. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Bering, J. M. (2006). The folk psychology of souls. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29(05), 453-462. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Bering, J. M. y Bjorklund, D. F. (2004). The natural emergence of reasoning about the afterlife as a developmental regularity. Developmental Psychology, 40, 217-233. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Putnam. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Darwin, C. (2012[1871]). El origen del hombre. Barcelona: Crítica. | spa |
dc.relation.references | De Villiers-Botha, T. (2019). Haidt et al.’s case for moral pluralism revisited. Philosophical Psychology, https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2019.1688776 | spa |
dc.relation.references | DeGrazia, D. (2008). Moral status As a Matter of Degree?, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, XLVI, 181-198. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Dwyer, S. (2006). How good is the linguistic analogy? En Carruthers, P., Laurence, S. y Stich, S. (Eds.), The innate mind, Vol. 2: culture and cognition (pp. 237-255). Oxford: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Fiske, A. P. (1991). Structures of social life. New York: The Free Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Flanagan, O. (2017). The Geography of Morals: Varieties of moral possibility. Nueva York: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Friman, P. C., Allen, K. D., Kerwin, M. L. E. y Larzelere, R. (1993). Changes in modern psychology: A citation analysis of the Kuhnian displacement thesis. American Psychologist, 48, 658-664. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Geertz, C. (1994). The Uses of Diversity. Assessing Cultural Anthropology, 454-367. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gibbard, A. (1992). Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: a Theory of Normative Judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Glenn, A. L., Iyer, R., Graham, J., Koleva, S. y Haidt, J. (2009). Are all types of morality compromised in psychopathy? Journal of Personality Disorders, 23, 384-398. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Glover, J. (2018). Humanidad e inhumanidad: Una historia moral del siglo XX. Barcelona: Cátedra. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Goodpaster, K. E. (1978). On being morally considerable. The Journal of Philosophy, 75, 308-325. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Goodwin, G. (2015). Experimental Approaches to Moral Standing. Philosophy Compass 10/11, 914926. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Graham, J., Haidt, J. y Nosek, B. A. (2009). Liberals and conservatives rely on different sets of moral foundations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96(5), 1029-1046. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Graham, J., Koleva, S., Iyer, R., Haidt, J., Motyl, M., Wojcik, S. P. y Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral foundations theory: The Pragmatic Validity of moral Pluralism. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 47, 55. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, H. M., Gray, K. y Wegner, D. M. (2007). Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 315, 619. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, K., Knobe, J., Sheskin, M., Bloom. P. y Barrett, L. F. (2011). More than a body: Mind perception and the nature of objectification. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 101(6), 1207-1220. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, K. y Schein, C. (2016). No absolutism here: Harm predicts moral judgment 30x better than disgust—Commentary on Scott, Inbar y Rozin (2016). Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11, 325-329. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, K. y Schein, C. (2012a). Two minds vs. two philosophies: Mind perception defines morality and dissolves the debate between deontology and utilitarianism. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3, 405-423. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, K., Schein, Ch. y Ward, A. F. (2014). The myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition: Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suffering. Journal of Experimental Psychology, General, 143, 1600-1615. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, K. y Ward, A. F. (2011). The harm hypothesis: Perceived harm unifies morality. Manuscript under review. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, K. y Wegner, D. M. (2016). The Mind Club: Who Thinks, What Feels, and Why It Matters. New York: Penguin Putnam Inc. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, K. y Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral typecasting: Divergent perceptions of moral agents and moral patients. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96(3), 505-520. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gray, K. Young, L. y Waytz, A. (2012b). Mind Perception Is the Essence of Morality. Psychological Inquiry, 23, 101-124. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Greene, J. D. (2015). The rise of moral cognition. Cognition, 135, 39-42. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Greene, J. D. y Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where) does moral judgement work. Trends in Cognitive Science, 6, 517-523. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Gunnthorsdottir, A. (2001). Physical attractiveness of an animal species as a decision factor for its preservation. Anthrozoos: A Multidisciplinary Journal of the Interactions of People and Animals, 14, 204-215. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional Dog and its Rational Tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, (4), 814-834. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. (2003). The moral emotions. En Scherer &y Goldsmith (Eds.), Handbook of affective science (pp. 852-870), . Oxford: Oxford University Press.. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. (2006). The happiness Hypothesis: Finding Modern Truth in Ancientic Wisdo. New York: Basic Books. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. (2007). The new Synthesis in Moral Psychology. Science, 316, 5827, -5998. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. (2012). The Righteous Mind. Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group. Edición de Kindle. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F. y Murphy, S. (2000). Moral dumbfounding: When intuitionfinds no reason. Manuscrito no publicado, University of Virginia, Charlottesville. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. y Graham, J. (2007). When morality opposes justice: Conservatives have moral intuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social Justice Research, 20(1), 98-116. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. y Hersh, M. (2001). Sexual Morality: The Cultures and Reasons of Liberals and Conservatives. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 31, 191-221. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. y Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: How innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 55-66. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. y Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind: How five sets of innate intuitions guide the development of many culture-specific virtues, and perhaps even modules. En P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, y S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind Vol. 3 (pp. 367-391). New York: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. y Joseph, C. (2008). The moral mind: How five sets of innate intuitions guide the development of many culture-specific virtues, and perhaps even modules. En P. Carruthers et al. (Eds.), The innate mind (pp. 367- 444). New York: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. y Kesebir, S. (2010). Morality. En S. Fiske, G. Gilbert, y G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology, 5th ed. (pp. 797-832). Hoboken: Wiley. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J. y Koller, S. (1994). Julgamento Moral nos Estados Unidos e no Brasil: Uma Visão Intuicionista. Psicologia: Reflexão e Crítica, 7(1), 75-90. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Haidt, J., Koller, S. y Dias, M. (1993). Affect, Culture, and Morality, or Is It Wrong to Eat Your Dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 613-628. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Hannikainen, I. y Rosas, A. (2019). Rationalization and Reflection Differentially Modulate Prior Attitudes Toward the Purity Domain. Cognitive Science, 43, e12747. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Hardin, R. (1995). One for all: The logic of group conflict. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The Concept of Law. London, Oxford: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Hauser, M. D. (2006). Moral minds: How nature designed our universal sense of right and wrong. London: Abacus. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Hazlitt, H. (1964). The foundations of morality. Princeton: D. Van Nostrand Company Inc. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Hegel, G. W. (2010[1793]). Líneas fundamentales de la filosofía del derecho. Madrid: Gredos. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Hume, D. (1976[1757]). The Natural History of Religion: Dialogues concerning natural religion / David Hume. Oxford: Clarendon Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Hume, D. (2005[1738]). Tratado de la naturaleza humana: Autobiografía. Madrid: Tecnos. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Hume, D. (2014[1777]). Investigación sobre los principios de la moral. Madrid: Alianza. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D. A. y Bloom, P. (2009). Conservatives are more easily disgusted than liberals. Cognition and Emotion, 23(4), 714-725. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Kant, I. (1996). Fundamentación de la metafísica de las costumbres (FMC). Barcelona: Ariel. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Kant, I. (2002). Crítica de la razón práctica. Salamanca: Sígueme. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Kelly, D., Stich, S., Haley, K., Eng, S. y Fessler, D. (2007). Harm, affect, and the moral/ conventional distinction. Mind y Language, 22(2), 117-131. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Killen, M. y Stangor, C. (2001). Children’s social reasoning about inclusion and exclusion in gender and race peer group contexts. Child Development, 72(1), 174-186. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Knobe, J. y Nichols, S. (2008). Experimental philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Knobe, J. y Prinz, J. (2007). Intuitions About Consciousness: Experimental Studies. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 67-83. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Kohlberg, L. (1976). Moral Stages and Moralization: The Cognitive-Developmental Approach. T. Licona (Ed.). Moral Development and Behavior: Theory, Research, and Social Issues. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Kohlberg, L. (1981). Essays on moral development: Vol 1. The philosophy of moral development: Moral stages and the idea of justice. San Francisco: Harper y Row. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Korsgaard, Ch. (2000). Las fuentes de la normatividad. México: Universidad Autónoma de México. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Kuhlmeier, V. A., Bloom, P. y Wynn, K. (2004). Do 5-month-old infants see humans as material objects? Cognition, 94(1), 95-103. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Laham, S. (2009). Expanding the moral circle: inclusion and exclusion mindset and the circle of moral regard. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45, 250-253 | spa |
dc.relation.references | Lee, J. y Nucci, L. (1993). Morality and personal auton- omy. En G. Noam y T. Wren, The moral self (pp. 124-148). Massachusetts: Massachusetts Institute of Techonology. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Lodish, H., Berk, A. y Kaiser, C. A. (2007). Molecular Cell Biology. New York: W.H. Freeman and Company. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Luque, P. (2011). Las dos vías del realismo moral. Discusiones, 10, 275-283. | spa |
dc.relation.references | MacIntyre, A. C. (1981). After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Indiana: University of Notte Dame Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | MacIntyre, A. C. (2013). Tras la virtud. Barcelona: Austral. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Markus, H.R. y Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: Implications for cognition, emotion, and motivation. Psychological Review, 98, 224-253. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Mill, J. S. (2001[1859]). Autobiography: Essay on liberty. Norwalk, Conn: Easton Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Miller, J. G. y Bersoff, D. M. (1992). Culture and moral judgment: How are conflicts between justice and interpersonal responsibilities resolved? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 541-554. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Miller, J. G., Bersoff, D. M. y Harwood, R. L. (1990). Perceptions of social responsibilities in India and the United States: Moral imperatives or personal decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 58, 33-47. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Miller, L. M. (2007). Coordinación y acción colectiva. Revista Internacional de Sociología, 45(46),161-183. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Moll, J., Zahn, R., De Oliveira-Souza, R., Krueger, F. y Grafman, J. (2005). Opinion: the neural basis of human moral cognition. Nat Rev Neurosci, 6, 799-809. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Montaigne, M. (2014). Ensayos. Barcelona: Galaxia Gutenberg. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Moore, G. E. (2018[1903]). Principia ethica. México: UNAM, Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Moore, W. H. (1995). Rational Rebels: Overcoming the Free-Rider Problem. Political Research Quarterly, 48, 417-454. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Müller-Lyer, F. C. (1889). Optische urteilstäuschungen. Archiv für Anatomie und Physiologie, Physiologische Abteilung, 263-270. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Murphy, J. G. (1965). The Highest Good as Content for Kant’s Ethical Formalism (Beck «versus» Silber). Kant-Studien, 56(1), 107. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Nichols, S. (2004) Sentimental rules: On the natural foundations of moral judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Nucci L. (1982). Conceptual Development in the Moral and Conventional Domains: Implications for Values. Review of Educational Research, 52(1), 93-122. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Nucci, L. (2001). Education in the moral domain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Nucci, L. (2003). La dimensión moral en la educación. Bilbao: Desclée de Brouwer SA. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Nussbaum, M. C. (2006). El ocultamiento de lo humano: Repugnancia, vergüenza y ley. Madrid: Katz. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Nussbaum, M. C. (2008). Paisajes del pensamiento: La inteligencia de las emociones. Barcelona: Paidós. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Nussbaum, M. C. (2012). Las fronteras de la justicia: Consideraciones sobre la exclusión. Barcelona: Paidós. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Osofsky, M. J., Bandura, A. y Zimbardo, P. G. (2005). The role of moral disengagement in the execution process. Law and Human Behavior, 29, 371-393. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Piaget, J. (1987[1932]). El criterio moral en el niño. Barcelona: Martínez Roca. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Piazza, J. y Landy, J. (2013). “Lean not on your own understanding”: Belief that morality is founded on divine authority and non-utilitarian moral thinking. Judgment and Decision Making, 8(6), 639-661. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Platón. (1985). Diálogos: Critón; Eutifrón; Ion; Lisis; Cármides; Hipias Mayor; Hipias Menor; Laques; Protágoras. Madrid: Gredos. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Pluhar, E. (1987). Moral Agents and Moral Patients. Between the Species, 4(1), 32-45. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Posada-Gilède, R. (2018). Creciendo en entornos violentos: influencia del contexto en el desarrollo moral. En E. Dulcey-Ruiz, C. J. Pwerales-Quenza y R. Posada-Gilède (Eds.), Envejecimiento: del nacer al morir. Bogotá: Siglo del Hombre. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Prinz, J. (2007). The emotional construction of moral. Nueva York: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Rachels, R. (1995). El subjetivismo. En P. Singer, Compendio de ética. Madrid: Alianza. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Rai, T. S. y Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychology is relationship regulation: Moral motives for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportionality. Psychology Review, 118(1), 57-75. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Rosas, A. (2000). Explicación y justificación: hacia el naturalismo en la filosofía moral. En J., Ramos, J. y Rosas, A. Mentes reales: La ciencia cognitiva y la naturalización de la mente (pp. 101-118). Bogotá: Siglo del Hombre / Universidad Nacional de Colombia. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Rosas, A. (2011). Ética Evolucionista: o enfoque adaptacionista da cooperação humana. En P. Abrantes, Filosofia da Biologia (pp. 296-314). São Paulo: Editores. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Rosas, A. (2013). Harm, Reciprocity and the Moral Domain. En V. Karakostas y D. Dicks (Eds.), Perspectives and Foundational Problems in Philosophy of Science, 493-502. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Royzman, E. B., Leeman, R. F. y Baron, J. (2009). Unsentimental ethics: Towards a content- specific account of the moral-conventional distinction. Cognition, 112(1), 159-174. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Rozin, P. y Fallon, A. (1997). A perspective on disgust. Psychological Review, 94, 23-41. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Rozin, P., Haidt, J. y McCauley, C. (1993). Disgust. En M. Lewis y J. Haviland (Eds.), The handbook of emotions (pp. 575-594). New York: Guilford Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Russell, B. (1927). Philosophy. New York: Norton. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Santos, M. y Venturá, T. P. (2009). El inicio de la vida de un nuevo ser humano desde la perspectiva científica biológica. Ars. Médica. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Sapontzis, S. F. (1987). Morals, Reason and Animals. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Schein, C., Goranson, A. y Gray, K. (2015). The uncensored truth about morality. The Psychologist, 28, 982-985. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Schein, C. y Gray, K. (2017). The Theory of Dyadic Morality: Reinventing Moral Judgment by Redefining Harm. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 1-39. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Schein, C., Ritter, R. S. y Gray, K. (2016). Harm mediates the disgust-immorality link. Emotion, 16(6), 862-876. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G.L. y Jordan, A. H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judgement. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 1096-1109. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Sexto Empírico. (2002). Esbozos Pirrónicos. Madrid: Gredos. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Shweder, R. A. (1990). In defense of moral realism: Reply to Gabennesch. Child Development, 61, 2060-2067. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Shweder, R. A. (1991). Thinking through cultures: Expeditions in cultural psychology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Shweder, R. A. (2002). The nature of morality: The category of bad acts. Medical Ethics, 9. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Shweder, R. y Haidt, J. (1993). The future of moral psychology: Truth, intuition, and the pluralist Way. En B. Puka, Moral development: A compendium (pp. 360-367). New York y London: Garland. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Shweder, R. A., Mahapatra, M. y Miller, J. (1987). Culture and moral development. En J. Kagan y S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence of morality in young children (pp. 1-83). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M. y Park, L. (1997). The “Big Three” of Morality (Autonomy, Community, Divinity) and the “Big Three”. Explanations of Suffering. En A. Brandt y P.Rozin (Eds.), Morality and Health (pp. 120-169). New York: Routledge. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Shweder, R. A. y Sullivan, M. A. (1993). Cultural psychology: Who needs it?”. Annual Review of Psychology, 44, 497-52. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Silva, G., Reyes, G., Peña, G. y Rosas, A. (2021). La noción de daño y su rol en los juicios morales. Un debate abierto. Daimon: Revista Internacional de Filosofía. 82, 2021, 157-170. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Singer, M. (1961). Generalization in Ethics. London: Eyre and Spottiswoode. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Singer, P. (1981). The expanding circle. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Singer, P. (2009). Ética práctica. Madrid: Akal. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Sinnott-Armstrong, W. y Wheatley, T. (2011). Moral judgments are not unified: Why moral psychology needs a taxonomic approach. Manuscript under review. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Smetana, J. (1993). Children’s conceptions of social rules. The Child As Psychologist, 111-141. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Smetana, J., (2006). Social-cognitive domain theory: Consistencies and variations in children’s moral and social judgments. Handbook of Moral Development, 119-155. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Smetana, J., Braeges, J. L. y Yau. J. (1991). Doing what you say and saying what you do: Reasoning about adolescent-parent conflict in interviews and interactions. Journal of Adolescent Research, 6, 276-95. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Smith, R. P., Gitau, R., Glover, V. y Fisk, N. M. (2000). Pain and stress in the human fetus. European Journal of Obstetrics y Gynecology and Reproductive Biology, 92(1), 161-165. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Sperber, D. (2005). Modularity and relevance: How can a massively modular mind be flexible and context-sensitive? En P. Carruthers et al. (Eds.), The innate mind: Structure and contents (pp. 53-68). New York: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Sripada, C. H. y Stich, S. (2006). A Framework for the psychology of norms. En P. Carruthers et al. (Eds.), The innate mind: Culture and cognition. New York: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Stangor, C. y Ruble, D. N. (1989). Differential influences of gender schemata and gender constancyon children’s information processing and behavior. Social Cognition, 7(4), 353-372. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Stevenson, C. L. (1981). El significado emotivo de los términos éticos. En Ayer, A. El positivismo lógico (pp. 269-286). México: Fondo de Cultura Económica. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Stich, S., Fessler, D. y Kelly, D. (2009). On the morality of harm: A response to Sousa, Holbrook and Piazza. Cognition, 113, 93-97. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Stone, C. D. (2010). Should trees have standing?: Law, morality, and the environment. New York, N.Y: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Stroud, B. (1995). Hume. México: Universidad Nacional Autónoma. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Sytsma, J. y Machery, E. (2012). Two conceptions of subjective experience. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3, 303-324. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Taylor, C. (1996). La explicación y la razón práctica. En M. Nussbaum y A. Sen (Comps.), La calidad de vida (pp. 274-303). México: Fondo de Cultura Económica. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Tomasello, M. y Vaish, A. (2013). Origins of human cooperation and morality. Annual Review of Psychology, 64(1), 231-255. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Tovar, J. O. y Ostrosky, F. (2013). Mentes criminales ¿eligen el mal? Estudios de cómo se genera el juicio moral. México: Manual Moderno, Kindle. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Trivers, R. (1971). The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 46(1), 3557. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Turiel, E. (1979). Distinct conceptual and developmental domains: social convention and morality. In En H. Howe and C. Keasey (edsEds.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, 1977: Social Cognitive Development , vol. 25 (pp. 77-116). Lincoln : University of Nebraska Press, 77—116. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Turiel, E. (1983). The Development of social Knowledge: Morality and Convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Turiel, E. (1989). Domain-specific social judgments and domain ambiguities. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 35, 89-114. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Turiel, E. (1998). The development of morality. In En N. Eisenberg (Ed.), W. Damon (Series Ed.), Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 3. Social, emotional, and personality development. (5th ed., (pp. 863-932). New York: Wiley. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Turiel, E. (2002). The culture of morality: social Social development, context and conflict. Wainryb: Cambridge University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Turiel, E., Hildebrant, C. y Wainryb, C. (1991). Judging social issues: Difficulties, inconsistencies, and consistencies. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 56, 1-103. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Turiel, E., Killen, M. y Helwig, C. (1987). Morality: Its structure, functions, and vagaries. En J. Kagan y S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence of morality in young children (pp. 155-244). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Warren, M. (2000). Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things. New York: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Waytz, A., Gray, K., Epley, N. y Wegner, D. M. (2010). Causes and consequences of mind perception. Trends in Cognitive Science, 14, 383-388. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Waytz, A. y Young, L. (2012). The Group-Member Mind Tradeoff: Attributing Mind to Groups Versus Group Members, Psychological Science, 23, 77-85. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Wegner, D. M. y Gray, K. J. (2016). The mind club: Who thinks, what feels, and why it matters. New York: Penguin Random House. Kindle. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Wellman, H. M. (1990). The Child’s Theory of Mind. Massachusetts: MIT Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Westbury, H. R. y Neumann, D. L. (2008). Empathy-related responses to moving film stimuli depicting human and non-human animal targets in negative circumstances. Biological Psychology, 78, 66-74. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Wheatley, T. y Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotically induced disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science, 16, 780-784. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Wong, D. B. (1995). Pluralistic Relativism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 20, 378-399. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Wong, D. B. (2006). Natural Moralities. Oxford: Oxford University Press. | spa |
dc.relation.references | Yáñez, J., Perdomo, A. (2009). Los dominios del desarrollo sociomoral: una nueva propuesta sobre el desarrollo. Horizonte Pedagógico, 11(1), 55-66. | spa |
dc.rights | Derechos reservados - Universidad Nacional de Colombia | spa |
dc.rights.accessrights | info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess | spa |
dc.rights.license | Atribución-CompartirIgual 4.0 Internacional | spa |
dc.rights.spa | Acceso abierto | spa |
dc.rights.uri | http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/ | spa |
dc.subject.ddc | 100 - Filosofía y Psicología::101 - Teoría de la filosofía | spa |
dc.subject.ddc | 170 - Ética (Filosofía moral)::171 - Sistemas éticos | spa |
dc.subject.ddc | 150 - Psicología::155 - Psicología diferencial y del desarrollo | spa |
dc.subject.proposal | Moral Judgment | eng |
dc.subject.proposal | Juicio moral | spa |
dc.subject.proposal | Estatus moral | spa |
dc.subject.proposal | Moral Status | eng |
dc.subject.proposal | Entidades morales | spa |
dc.subject.proposal | Moral Entities | eng |
dc.subject.proposal | Daño moral | spa |
dc.subject.proposal | Moral harm | eng |
dc.subject.proposal | Moral Psychology | eng |
dc.subject.proposal | Psicología moral | spa |
dc.subject.proposal | Mtaethics | eng |
dc.subject.proposal | Metaética | spa |
dc.subject.proposal | Experimental Philosophy | eng |
dc.subject.proposal | Filosofía experimental | spa |
dc.title | La percepción de daño intencional y su papel en los juicios morales condenatorios | spa |
dc.title.alternative | The perception of intentional harm and its role in damning moral judgments | spa |
dc.type | Trabajo de grado - Doctorado | spa |
dc.type.coar | http://purl.org/coar/resource_type/c_db06 | spa |
dc.type.coarversion | http://purl.org/coar/version/c_ab4af688f83e57aa | spa |
dc.type.content | Text | spa |
dc.type.driver | info:eu-repo/semantics/doctoralThesis | spa |
dc.type.version | info:eu-repo/semantics/acceptedVersion | spa |
oaire.accessrights | http://purl.org/coar/access_right/c_abf2 | spa |